orgtheory.net

the missing motivation

Brayden

Tom Bozzo drew my attention to a new AER paper by George Akerlof with the provocative title, “The Missing Motivation in Macroeconomics.” (An earlier version of the paper can be found here.) In the paper Akerlof argues that macroeconomics lacks good micro-theoretical foundations for understanding variation in people’s behavior. Neoclassical macroeconomics is based on very narrow assumptions about individuals’ utility functions. Akerlof says that this view of behavior isn’t very “realistic,” however, because in most observable situations people do not make decisions according to some simple utility function. Rather than making excuses for empirical observations, Akerlof says that economists need better theories about what drives human interest. The answer: sociology, of course.

But as early as the beginning of the Twentieth Century, Vilfredo Pareto pointed out that such characterizations of utility missed important aspects of motivation. According to Pareto people typically have opinions as to how they should, or how they should not, behave. They also have views regarding how others should, or should not, behave. Such views are called norms, and they may be individual as well as social. The role of norms can be easily represented in peoples’ preferences by modifying the utility function to include losses in utility insofar as they, or others, fail to live up to their standards.

Sociology has a further concept that gives an easy and natural way to add those norms to the utility function. Sociologists say that people have an ideal for how they should or should not behave. Furthermore that ideal is often conceptualized in terms of the behavior of someone they know, or some exemplar who they do not know. The standard utility function is then modified by adding a loss in utility dependent on the distance of behavior from that ideal.

Akerlof goes on to review a substantial (for an economics journal) amount of sociology that deals with how norms influence what people see as appropriate or desirable behavior. Included in his review is Randy Hodson’s research on how norms affect employee satisfaction, Bourdieu’s conception of class distinctions as a motivator of consumption, and Weber’s classic take on Protestants’ desire to save rather than spend. The paper’s main objective is to show economists that “norms” (which he sees as the unifying concept of sociology) fundamentally shape people’s interests and thereby determine spending and saving patterns.

Akerlof is speaking to economists and so the conceptual nuances of sociology are not that important to him. For example, most sociologists, especially contemporary cultural sociologists, would probably not use the concept of “norms” to explain behavior as loosely as Akerlof does here. Inasmuch as certain social prescriptions are internalized, they function more like scripts or cultural rules. Other sociologists conceive of norms as situational. Their effectiveness really depends on the relationship of the exchanging actors. Alternatively, some sociologists now espouse that norms are just one kind of cultural resource that can be accessed to help accomplish other goals (e.g. achieving a higher social status). The logic of this argument, somewhat ironically, is much closer to that of rational choice theorists who see interests as inherent and norms/rules/cultural repertoires as serving those interests.

Instead, what Akerlof seems to be doing here is returning to a more elegant version of Parsonian sociology, in which norms shape social action and prescribe certain behaviors. But rather than try to build up a wall or division of labor between economists and sociologists, as did Parsons, Akerlof is calling for a melding of the two disciplines, helping economists to see that sociologists have identified a theoretical mechanism that can feed directly into economists’ view of utility.

Written by brayden king

April 18, 2007 at 2:44 pm

Posted in brayden, sociology

6 Responses

Subscribe to comments with RSS.

  1. […] Mark Graber wrote an interesting post today onHere’s a quick excerptIn the paper Akerlof argues that macroeconomics lacks good micro-theoretical foundations for understanding variation in people’s behavior. Neoclassical macroeconomics is based on very narrow assumptions about individuals’ utility … […]

    Like

  2. Well, at least Akerloff is caught up to sociological theory circa 1937 (or maybe 1951 if you want to be charitable). The problem is that most of the action in sociological theory since then has been to get away from the Parsonian problematic. Granovetter’s (1985) much ignored first half of his article, tried to make the case that oscillations between the oversocialized and the undersocialized views, were fruitless and that his own relational via media may have been one way to escape it.

    I am of the humble opinion that some the underlying theory behind the normative view (something constrains behavior, and that something is social) is correct; even if the theory is wrong as to what the contents of those constraints are: norms expressible in sentential tokens of the form if (in situation X) then (perform action Y).

    I am even more skeptical that the formal apparatus of expected utility theory coupled to a sociological conception of norms is the answer to what ails us. For once that has already been proposed and done by James Coleman (1990) for instance.

    Like

    Omar

    April 18, 2007 at 3:07 pm

  3. In my EJW critique of Akerlof’s earlier work with Kranton, I pointed out that he often dumps nuance of sociological research so much that he actually misreads the research. Also, my sense of Akerlof’s intellectual project is that he wants to appeal to sociology so he can promote a Coleman-esque project, as Omar implies. It is notable that while he cites sociology, he rarely works with sociologists. What all of this suggests is that Akerlof isn’t so much interested in a real rapport between soc and econ, but more interested in using soc research to justify relatively minor deviations from neo-classical models (e.g.,variations in what counts as a preference worth studying).

    Like

    Fabio Rojas

    April 18, 2007 at 3:27 pm

  4. I agree with both of your points, but I think Akerlof, perhaps unintentionally, draws attention to a major strength of sociology – the ability to describe and predict motivations for behavior. Self-interest is too vacuous a concept to describe or predict much of anything (as you can create a post hoc story to explain why any behavior was in the interest of the actor). In contrast, sociologists think that social structures, institutions, and even norms shape how those self-interests are defined. In this sense, sociologists have a lot to offer the rest of the social science world.

    Like

    brayden

    April 18, 2007 at 3:38 pm

  5. If Akerlof’s main contribution in this debate is to help economists see the importance of institutions/structure, etc., I can’t be that critical. But still, it would be nice to see some deeper synthesizing of soc and econ, beyond the Coleman “norms” program. Anybody out there who can make that jump? A Chosen One who can help economists break out of their self-imposed neo-classical Matrix?

    Like

    Fabio Rojas

    April 18, 2007 at 4:08 pm

  6. From the introductory section of the paper, it is easy to see that Akerloff’s notion of norms is fairly fuzzy. He uses the terms to refer to both “values” and “ideals” in the old Parsonian sense, in addition to garden variety “norms” (which are usually situational or specify a fairly well established class of situations in which they apply). Thus, in the Friedan example the “norm” of being a housewife is closer to the notion of an identity standard in sociological identity control theory, while the “utility” that one might get from gift-giving only has a faint relation to the usualy normative motivation for gift giving isolated by sociologists and anthropologists, which is Gouldner’s “norm of reciprocity.”

    There is a brilliant 1993 paper by Thomas Fararo in Sociological Theory in which he attempts to unify the formal framework of Foundations of Social Theory with the Parsonian AGIL scheme. It becomes fairly clear that a “normative” reconsideration of purposive action a la Parsons, can best be formalized through recourse to a view of the actor as a cybernetic control system. Parsons did this metaphorically (as he was very familiar with the cybernetic control theory that was being developed by Wiener and others in the OR think tanks), but Fararo does that formally.

    Fararo notes that in the FST conception, the notion of interest is not tied to any particular “economic” interest, since this is only as special case of “interest in general.” Since interests are the “motivational” equivalent of utility in the Coleman framework, a generalization of the expected utility formalism to account for interest in all kinds of resources implies the addition of a motivational component to the neoclassical framework. Fararo says:

    The other primitive relation in the FST model’s theory template is interests. Earliers I emphasized that this concept is generalized; it is attached to certain exponents in a form of utility function that enables deductive fertility in the FST model. Preconceptions about the meaning of interests should be put aside to enable flexible use of the template. Intuitive ideas associated with this term however, suggest how it can be made to correspond with the state variables of the AGIL model. In fact, interests correspond directly with the G level, that of motivation: Coleman regards the maximization of utility as a motivation assumption (304).*

    And Fararo concludes with these comments in terms of the relationship between economics and sociology,

    In relation to economics, two routes may be taken. One involves what has been called embeddedness…Any empirical economy is only a part of a society, implying that institutional conditions as well as interpersonal networks mediate concrete economic transactions. This is the sociology of the economy, or (as it is now becoming popular to say) “economic sociology.”

    The other route involves abstraction and generalization along the lines taken in the FST model. A general mathematical theory abstracted from the general equilibrim theory in economics and is given a more general interpretation. The economic interpretation becomes a special case. The abstract theory is also extended, in a logical sense, to encompass wider but still abstractly understood phenomena…(311).

    *Parsons to English Dictionary:
    A: adaptation
    G: goal-attainment
    I: integration
    L: latent pattern maintenance

    Why “latent” pattern maintenance you ask? No particular reason, just that if you leave it as “pattern maintenance” the scheme’s acronym reads as PIGA when read the way it was supposed to (that’s why Randall Collins calls it the LIGA scheme) from cultural values at the “highest” levels of the control hierarchy to lowly behavioral adaptation to the material environment at the lowest level.

    Like

    Omar

    April 18, 2007 at 7:14 pm


Comments are closed.